commentable: true protected: numbering: type: repopath: mathjax: true categories: Analysis tags: Analysis keywords: Fundemental-Math description: Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice (ZFC) is a widely accepted formal system for set theory. It consists of nine axioms. mermaid: true highlight: true status: Archive

Axiomatized Set Theory: ZFC Axioms

Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice (ZFC) is a widely accepted formal system for set theory. It consists of nine axioms, which are:

Extensionality

The Extensionality Axiom is one of the fundamental axioms of ZFC set theory. It states that two sets are equal if and only if they have the same elements.

xy[z(zxzy)x=y]\forall x \forall y [\forall z (z \in x \Leftrightarrow z \in y) \Rightarrow x=y]

This means that if two sets have exactly the same elements, then they are identical sets. Conversely, if two sets are identical, then they have exactly the same elements. This may seem like a trivial statement, but it is actually quite powerful and fundamental to the rest of set theory.

The Extensionality Axiom allows us to reason about sets purely in terms of their elements. If we know the elements of two sets, we can determine whether or not they are the same set. It also allows us to define sets by specifying their elements. For example, we can define the set of all even natural numbers as follows:

{nNn is even}\{n \in \mathbb{N} \mid n \text{ is even}\}

This notation specifies a set by defining its elements (in this case, all even natural numbers). By the Extensionality Axiom, we know that this set is unique and well-defined, since any two sets with exactly the same even natural numbers as elements are the same set.

In summary, the Extensionality Axiom allows us to reason about sets purely in terms of their elements, and to define sets by specifying their elements.

Regularity

The Regularity Axiom is one of the nine axioms of ZFC set theory. It states that every non-empty set has an element that is disjoint from it.

x[y(yx)z(zxzx=)]\forall x [\exists y (y \in x) \Rightarrow \exists z (z \in x \land z \cap x = \varnothing)]

This may seem like a strange statement at first, but it is actually quite intuitive. The idea is that if we have a non-empty set, then there must be an element in it that is "minimal" in some sense. That is, there must be an element that has no other elements "beneath" it in the set hierarchy.

One possible way to think about this is in terms of membership graphs. Given a set xx, we can draw a graph where each element of xx is a node, and there is an edge from node aa to node bb if and only if aa is an element of bb. This graph is called the membership graph of xx. The Regularity Axiom tells us that every non-empty set has a node in its membership graph that has no incoming edges.

Another way to think about the Regularity Axiom is in terms of the "rank" of a set. The rank of a set xx, denoted rank(x)rank(x), is the smallest ordinal α\alpha such that xVαx \subseteq V_\alpha, where VαV_\alpha is the α\alpha-th level of the cumulative hierarchy of sets. The Regularity Axiom tells us that every non-empty set has an element with rank strictly less than the rank of the set itself. Intuitively, this means that every set has a "minimal" element in terms of the level of the cumulative hierarchy it belongs to.

The Regularity Axiom has several important consequences and applications in set theory. For example, it implies that there are no infinite descending chains of sets with respect to the inclusion relation. That is, if we have a sequence of sets x1x2x3x_1 \supseteq x_2 \supseteq x_3 \supseteq \cdots, then this sequence must eventually stabilize, meaning that there is some kk such that xk=xk+1=xk+2=x_k = x_{k+1} = x_{k+2} = \cdots. This fact has important applications in the study of well-founded relations and recursion theory.

In summary, the Regularity Axiom ensures the existence of "minimal" elements in sets, and has important consequences for the structure and behavior of sets and their membership graphs.

Pairing

The Axiom of Pairing is one of the nine axioms of ZFC set theory. It allows us to create a new set that contains exactly two given elements.

xyzw[wz(w=xw=y)]\forall x \forall y \exists z \forall w [w \in z \Leftrightarrow (w = x \lor w = y)]

This means that for any two sets xx and yy, there exists a set zz whose only elements are xx and yy. We can denote this set as {x,y}\{x,y\}.

The Axiom of Pairing allows us to create pairs of sets, which are fundamental building blocks in set theory. We can use pairs to define ordered pairs, Cartesian products, and other important constructs.

One important fact about pairs is that they are unordered. That is, {x,y}\{x,y\} and {y,x}\{y,x\} are considered to be the same set. This can be proved using the Axiom of Extensionality.

The Axiom of Pairing has several important consequences and applications in set theory. For example, it allows us to define binary relations as sets of ordered pairs. Given sets XX and YY, we can define a binary relation RR between XX and YY as a subset of the Cartesian product X×YX \times Y. This subset can be constructed using pairs and the Axiom of Separation.

Another application of the Axiom of Pairing is in the construction of the natural numbers. The natural number 00 can be defined as the empty set \varnothing, and each subsequent natural number n+1n+1 can be defined as the set {n}\{n\}, which contains only the previous natural number. Using this definition, we can construct the entire set of natural numbers using only the Axiom of Pairing and the Axiom of Union.

In summary, the Axiom of Pairing allows us to create pairs of sets and has important consequences for the construction of other fundamental constructs such as relations and natural numbers.

Union

The Axiom of Union is one of the nine axioms of ZFC set theory. It allows us to create a new set that contains all the elements of a collection of sets.

ABx[(xB)(yA)(xy)]\forall A \exists B \forall x [(x \in B) \Leftrightarrow (\exists y \in A) (x \in y)]

This means that for any set AA, there exists a set BB that contains exactly the elements of the sets that are members of AA. We can denote this set as A\bigcup A.

The Axiom of Union allows us to construct unions of sets, which are fundamental operations in set theory. We can use unions to define intersections, complements, and other important constructs.

One important fact about unions is that they are associative. That is, (AB)C=A(BC)(A \cup B) \cup C = A \cup (B \cup C) for any sets AA, BB, and CC. This can be proved using the Axiom of Extensionality.

The Axiom of Union has several important consequences and applications in set theory. For example, it allows us to define the intersection of two sets as the complement of their symmetric difference. Given sets AA and BB, we can define their intersection ABA \cap B as (AB)(AB)(BA)(A \cup B) - (A - B) - (B - A). This definition can be simplified using the Axiom of Union and the Axiom of Complement.

Another application of the Axiom of Union is in the construction of the hierarchy of sets. This hierarchy is defined recursively as follows: V0=V_0 = \varnothing, and for each ordinal α\alpha, Vα+1=VαV_{\alpha+1} = \bigcup V_\alpha. For limit ordinals λ\lambda, Vλ=α<λVαV_\lambda = \bigcup_{\alpha < \lambda} V_\alpha. Using this definition, we can construct a transfinite sequence of sets that includes all the sets in ZFC set theory.

In summary, the Axiom of Union allows us to construct unions of sets and has important consequences for the construction of other fundamental constructs such as intersections, complements, and the hierarchy of sets.

Power Set

The Axiom of Power Set is one of the nine axioms of ZFC set theory. It states that for any set AA, there exists a set P(A)P(A), called the power set of AA, that contains all the subsets of AA.

AP(A)B[(BA)(BP(A))]\forall A \exists P(A) \forall B [(B \subseteq A) \Rightarrow (B \in P(A))]

This means that for any set AA, there exists a set P(A)P(A) that contains all the subsets of AA. We can denote the power set of AA as P(A)\mathcal{P}(A).

The Axiom of Power Set allows us to construct a set that contains all the possible subsets of a given set. This is a crucial concept in set theory and has many applications. For example, we can use the power set to define operations like set difference and complement.

One important fact about the power set is that it is always larger than the original set. That is, P(A)>A|P(A)| > |A| for any set AA. This can be proved using the Axiom of Regularity and the Cantor's theorem.

The Axiom of Power Set has several important consequences and applications in set theory. For example, it allows us to define the Cartesian product of two sets. Given sets AA and BB, we can define their Cartesian product A×BA \times B as the set of all ordered pairs (a,b)(a,b) where aAa \in A and bBb \in B. This set can be constructed using the power set and other ZFC axioms.

Another application of the Axiom of Power Set is in the construction of the real numbers. The real numbers can be defined as the set of all Dedekind cuts, which are subsets of the rational numbers that partition the rational number line. The power set allows us to construct the set of all subsets of the rational numbers, which includes all the possible Dedekind cuts.

In summary, the Axiom of Power Set allows us to construct a set that contains all the possible subsets of a given set. This concept has many important applications in set theory, including the construction of the Cartesian product and the real numbers.

Axiom of Choice

The Axiom of Choice is one of the nine axioms of ZFC set theory. It states that given any collection of non-empty sets, there exists a way to choose exactly one element from each set in the collection.

A[Af:AAsuch thatf(A)AAA]\forall \mathcal{A} [\emptyset \notin \mathcal{A} \Rightarrow \exists f : \mathcal{A} \rightarrow \bigcup \mathcal{A}\, \text{such that}\, f(A) \in A\,\,\forall A \in \mathcal{A}]

This means that for any collection of non-empty sets A\mathcal{A}, there exists a function ff that assigns to each set in A\mathcal{A} exactly one element that belongs to that set. The Axiom of Choice is often written using the notation of set theory as follows:

A[AA]\forall \mathcal{A} [\emptyset \notin \mathcal{A} \Rightarrow \prod \mathcal{A} \neq \emptyset]

where A\prod \mathcal{A} denotes the Cartesian product of the sets in A\mathcal{A}.

The Axiom of Choice has many important consequences in mathematics, including in topology, analysis, algebra, and set theory. One of the most famous applications of the Axiom of Choice is in the proof of the Banach-Tarski paradox, which states that it is possible to decompose a solid ball into a finite number of pieces and then reassemble those pieces to form two solid balls of the same size as the original.

Despite its many applications, the Axiom of Choice is also controversial among mathematicians, as it implies the existence of non-constructive objects, and some argue that it violates intuition in certain cases. As a result, some mathematicians work in set theories that do not include the Axiom of Choice or only use it in specific contexts.

An alternative to the Axiom of Choice is the Axiom of Countable Choice, which states that given any countable collection of non-empty sets, there exists a way to choose one element from each set in the collection. This weaker form of the Axiom of Choice has many of the same applications but avoids some of the more controversial consequences of the full axiom.

Infinity

The Axiom of Infinity is one of the nine axioms of ZFC set theory. It states that there exists at least one set that contains the empty set and is closed under the successor operation.

N[NxN(x{x}N)]\exists \mathbb{N} [\emptyset \in \mathbb{N} \wedge \forall x \in \mathbb{N}(x\cup\{x\} \in \mathbb{N})]

This means that there exists a set N\mathbb{N} that contains the empty set \emptyset and is closed under the successor operation, which adds one element to a set. The axiom guarantees the existence of an infinite set, which is crucial in many areas of mathematics.

There are alternative descriptions of the Axiom of Infinity that are equivalent to the above statement. One such description is to say that there exists a set that contains the empty set and is closed under the power set operation:

S[Sx(xSP(x)S)]\exists S [\emptyset \in S \wedge \forall x (x\in S \Rightarrow \mathcal{P}(x)\in S)]

where P(x)\mathcal{P}(x) denotes the power set of xx, i.e., the set of all subsets of xx.

The Axiom of Infinity has many important consequences in mathematics, including in number theory, topology, and analysis. In particular, the axiom guarantees the existence of infinite sets, which are essential for the development of many mathematical concepts and structures.

It is worth noting that the Axiom of Infinity does not specify the size or structure of the infinite set it guarantees. In fact, there are many different infinite sets that satisfy the axiom, such as the set of natural numbers, the set of even numbers, or the set of all finite sets. This is one of the reasons why the axiom is considered a foundational principle of set theory.

Foundation

The Axiom of Foundation is one of the nine axioms of ZFC set theory. It is also known as the Axiom of Regularity. The axiom states that every non-empty set xx contains an element yy that is disjoint from xx.

x(y(yx)y(yxz(zyzx)))\forall x (\exists y (y\in x) \Rightarrow \exists y (y\in x \wedge \forall z(z \in y \Rightarrow z \notin x)))

In other words, every non-empty set xx has an element yy that is "earlier" than xx, in the sense that yy is not an element of xx and every element of yy is also "earlier" than xx. This prevents the existence of "cycles" in the membership relation \in, where a set is an element of itself or a member of a member of itself, which can lead to contradictions in set theory.

The Axiom of Foundation implies several important results in set theory, such as the existence of a well-founded relation on the class of all sets, and the fact that every set can be well-ordered. It also allows for the development of transfinite induction, which is a powerful tool in the study of infinite sets.

There are alternative descriptions of the Axiom of Foundation that are equivalent to the above statement. One such description is to say that every non-empty set xx has an element yy that is minimal with respect to the \in-relation:

x(y(yx)y(yx¬z(zyzx)))\forall x (\exists y (y\in x) \Rightarrow \exists y (y\in x \wedge \neg\exists z (z \in y \wedge z \in x)))

where ¬\neg denotes logical negation.

Overall, the Axiom of Foundation ensures the well-behaved nature of the membership relation \in, and leads to many important results in the study of sets and their properties.

Replacement

The Axiom of Replacement is one of the nine axioms of ZFC set theory. It allows us to construct a new set by applying a definable function to the elements of an existing set.

xy1y2yn(z(zx!wϕ(w,z,y1,y2,,yn))yz(zxϕ(y,z,y1,y2,,yn)))\forall x \forall y_1 \forall y_2 \cdots \forall y_n (\forall z(z \in x \Rightarrow \exists ! w \phi(w,z,y_1,y_2,\ldots,y_n)) \Rightarrow \exists y \forall z(z \in x \Rightarrow \phi(y,z,y_1,y_2,\ldots,y_n)))

In other words, for any set xx and definable function ϕ\phi, we can create a new set yy consisting of the outputs of ϕ\phi when applied to the elements of xx.

The Axiom of Replacement is a powerful tool in set theory, allowing us to construct new sets from old ones and proving many important results. It implies the existence of a set of all ordered pairs, as well as the existence of the power set of any set.

There are alternative descriptions of the Axiom of Replacement that are equivalent to the above statement. One such description is to say that if ϕ\phi is a function such that for every xx there exists a unique yy satisfying ϕ(x,y)\phi(x,y), then the range of ϕ\phi exists as a set:

ϕA(xA!yϕ(x,y)By(yBxAϕ(x,y)))\forall \phi \forall A (\forall x \in A \exists ! y \phi(x,y) \Rightarrow \exists B \forall y(y \in B \Leftrightarrow \exists x \in A \phi(x,y)))

where \Leftrightarrow denotes logical equivalence.

Overall, the Axiom of Replacement allows for the construction of new sets from old ones and leads to many important results in the study of sets and their properties.

These nine axioms, together with first-order logic, form the basis of ZFC set theory. They allow for the development of a wide range of mathematical concepts and provide a rigorous foundation for modern mathematics.

Compatibility of ZFC

Theorem: The nine axioms of the ZFC framework are compatible with each other, i.e., there is no contradiction between them.

Proof:

We will prove the compatibility of each pair of axioms:

Proof 1. Compatibility of Extensionality

Let AA be a set. By the Extensionality axiom, the set AA is uniquely determined by its elements, so we can define the set B=AB={A}. Now, by the Regularity axiom, there exists an element CBC\in B such that CB=C\cap B=\varnothing. Since CBC\in B, we have C=AC=A, so AA=A\cap{A}=\varnothing. This means that AA does not contain itself, which satisfies the Regularity axiom. Therefore, Extensionality and Regularity are compatible with each other.

Let AA and BB be sets. By the Pairing axiom, there exists a set C=A,BC={A,B}. Suppose for contradiction that CC is not uniquely determined by its elements, i.e., there exists a set DCD\neq C such that xCx\in C if and only if xDx\in D. Then, either ADA\in D and BDB\notin D, or ADA\notin D and BDB\in D. Without loss of generality, assume that ADA\in D and BDB\notin D. Then, by the Extensionality axiom, CDC\neq D, which is a contradiction. Therefore, Extensionality and Pairing are compatible with each other.

Let AA be a set. By the Union axiom, there exists a set B=AB=\bigcup A. Suppose for contradiction that BB is not uniquely determined by its elements, i.e., there exists a set CBC\neq B such that xBx\in B if and only if xCx\in C. Then, for all aAa\in A, aBa\subseteq B and aCa\subseteq C, so BCB\subseteq C and CBC\subseteq B. Therefore, B=CB=C, which is a contradiction. Therefore, Extensionality and Union are compatible with each other.

Let AA be a set. By the Power Set axiom, there exists a set B=P(A)B=\mathcal{P}(A). Suppose for contradiction that BB is not uniquely determined by its elements, i.e., there exists a set CBC\neq B such that xBx\in B if and only if xCx\in C. Then, for all aAa\subseteq A, aBa\in B if and only if aCa\in C, so B=CB=C, which is a contradiction. Therefore, Extensionality and Power Set are compatible with each other.

By the Infinity axiom, there exists an infinite set AA. By the Extensionality axiom, any two sets with the same elements are equal, so any infinite set AA has the same elements as any other infinite set. Therefore, there is no contradiction between Extensionality and Infinity.

The Foundation axiom states that every non-empty setAA contains an element that is disjoint from AA. This axiom is not affected by the Extensionality axiom, since the existence of a disjoint element is determined by the elements of the set, which are uniquely determined by the set's Extensionality.

The Replacement axiom states that given any set AA and any functional relation ff, there exists a set that contains the image of AA under ff. This axiom is not affected by the Extensionality axiom, since the image of AA under ff is uniquely determined by the Extensionality of AA and the properties of the functional relation ff.

The Axiom of Choice states that given any collection of non-empty sets, there exists a way to choose one element from each set in the collection. This axiom is also not affected by the Extensionality axiom, since the choice of elements is determined by the elements of the sets, which are uniquely determined by the sets' Extensionality.